I’ve had a few conversations recently about
writing reviews – something that I do fairly regularly and, truth be told,
rather enjoy. It can be tricky territory, for all the obvious reasons; one
author I know stopped doing them because he kept bumping into writers whose
work he’d been (shall we say) frank about. On the other hand, there’s the
danger of too cosy a job. So what’s the conscientious reviewer to do?
Having these conversations recently, I
found myself returning to one key idea: that the best reviews criticise on principle. (By ‘criticise’, I mean act
as a critic – which might, of course, include praise.) This has the advantage
of maximising the general interest and value of a review, by engaging in
discussion of something greater than any one individual work – and thereby
(hopefully) avoiding a limited ad hominem
perspective.
What, then, does it mean to criticise ‘on
principle’? As well as paying close attention to the detail of the work in question, I suppose that it means judging by reference to its wider implications. What does it add (or do) to the culture – and how? What does the pleasure (or displeasure) it provides say about the human mind? And – without getting too Kantian – what can we infer about the character and
potential of all such works? I.e.,
what does this book of poetry do for (or to) the idea of poetry in general?
This method considers the general (even the universal) in the particular – and the particular in the general. It gives the writer some credit. And it means the review stands a better chance of being worth
reading in its own right, too, because it becomes a place where principles –
whole matrices of ideas applicable in any number of ways – might be found and
articulated. Furthermore, such a method keeps the critic’s mind focused on quality – not in a static or dogmatic
sense, but the infinite ways in which a work might achieve value and authority.
And hence – ideally – both the poet and the critic end up looking for the same
thing.